192 Normat 60:4, 192 (2012)
Summary in English
Christer O. Kiselman, Euclid’s
straight lines (English)
What is a straight line? Primitive
notions are of course notoriously in-
tractable as to formal definitions, but
need to be understood through the way
they are actually used. The author ta-
kes as point of departure Euclid’s pro-
positions 27 and 16 in his first book.
The first gives a sucient criterion for
two lines to be parallel, the second sta-
tes that the exterior angle is larger than
any of the two opposite angles in a tri-
angle. From a strict logical point of view
the propositions do not follow from the
axioms, as one can give a model (the
projective plane) for which they do not
hold. Clearly Euclid made some implicit
assumptions. As Hilbert e t al. pointed
out about a century ago, Euclid ma-
de many implicit assumptions, which do
not, however, detract from his achieve-
ment, so the focus of interest is to try
and pinpoint more exactly how Euclid
really thought (as opposed to what he
wrote down). This leads the author
on an historical and linguistic odyssey,
with special emphasis on the notion of
’eutheia’ which can be understood as
meaning a line segment, a ray, or a line
indefinitely extended, and used in all
three meanings by Euclid. The notion of
infinite extension leads to philosophical
questions about potential versus actual
infinity, and how we in retrospect can
through the notion of equivalence clas-
ses speak about the infinite line without
specifying it as a concrete geometric ob-
ject unlike the finite line segment. Anot-
her is sue discussed, if briefly, is the le-
gitimacy of relying on visual diagrams
in formal deductive proofs. To use them
as support, be it for the imagination or
memory, is one thing, but to draw actu-
al conclusions from them, quite another
thing. Figures can be misleading espec-
ially when one draws planar diagrams of
geometrical configurations on a sphere
not to mention a non-orientable surface.
Was Euclid aware of the latter possibili-
ty? According to the author we can only
speculate.
Leif Önneflod, Comparison and
Change (English).
There is a discrepancy between m athe-
matical symbolism and what mathe-
matical concepts really me an. The for-
mer is a poor substitute for the lat-
ter. The problem is most acute in ele-
mentary instruction concerning the ba-
sic operations of arithmetic, le ading to
much confusion among pupils. Miscon-
ceptions may never be clarified, thus
sustaining into adulthood, becoming a
potential obstruction for using mathe-
matics in everyday situations. The ar-
ticle can be seen as an introduction to
a longer opus by the author in which he
gives a detailed and systematic explana-
tion of what it really means to perform
elementary arithmetic operations with
special emphasis on the didactic confu-
sions involved.
The former is a poor substitute for
the latter. T he problem is most acute in
elementary instruction concerning the
basic operations of arithmetic, leading
to much confusion among pupils (and
educators). Misconceptions may never
be clarified, thus sustaining into adult-
hood , becoming a pote ntial obstruc-
tion for using mathematics in everyday
situations. The article can be seen as
an introduction to a longer opus by the
author in which he gives a detailed and
systematic explanation of what it really
means to perform elementary arithme-
tic operations with special emphasis on
the didactic confusions involved.